"Reasonable Humans and
Animals: An Argument for Vegetarianism"
“It is easy for us to
criticize the prejudices of our grandfathers, from which our fathers freed
themselves. It is more difficult to distance ourselves from our own views, so
that we can dispassionately search for prejudices among the beliefs and values we
hold.”
- Peter Singer
"It's a matter of
taking the side of the weak against the strong, something the best people have
always done."
- Harriet Beecher Stowe
In my 15 or so years of experience of teaching philosophy, ethics and
logic courses, I have found that no topic brings out the rational and emotional
best and worst in people than ethical questions about the treatment of
animals. This is not surprising since, unlike questions about social policy and
about what other people should do,
moral questions about animals are personal.
As philosopher Peter Singer has observed, “For most human beings, especially in
modern urban and suburban communities, the most direct form of contact with
non-human animals is at mealtimes: we eat them.”[1] For
most of us, then, our own behavior is challenged when we reflect on the reasons
given to think that change is needed in our treatment of, and attitudes toward,
animals. That the issue is personal presents unique challenges, and great
opportunities, for intellectual and moral progress.
Here I
present some of the reasons given for and against taking animals seriously and
reflect on the role of reason in our lives. I examine the common assumption that there is nothing wrong with harming
animals -- causing them pain, suffering, and an early death – so they might be
eaten. We will see if moral “common sense” in this area can survive
critical scrutiny. Our method, useful for better understanding all ethical
debates, is to identify unambiguous and precise moral conclusions and make all
the reasons in favor of the conclusion explicit, leaving no assumption
unstated.
Harms
and Reasons
Why is the
treatment of animals a moral issue? Plutarch suggested an answer nearly two
thousand years ago when he reflected on the killing of animals for food:
But for the sake of some
little mouthful of flesh we deprive a soul of the sun and light, and of that
proportion of life and time it had been born into the world to enjoy.
The simple
answer is that animals are harmed by
the practices required to bring them to our plates, and harms need rational
defense. Chickens, pigs, cows, and other animals are conscious, can feel
pleasure and pain, and their lives can go better or worse, from their own point
of view. Raising and killing them is bad
for them: they experience pain, suffering, deprivation, boredom and an
early death. Everything is taken from
them so that they might be eaten. And this is true regardless of the conditions
they are raised in.
Let us consider the common view that, even
though it’s true that animals are harmed (indeed greatly harmed) by the practices required for meat eating, these practices are morally permissible nevertheless.
We will see that common arguments for this perspective all have premises that
are either false or in need of serious defense. The methods used in responding
to these arguments will prove useful for addressing further arguments and
objections beyond those discussed here.
Defending
Tradition
One of the
first things said is that it’s not wrong to harm animals for food because it’s
a “tradition”: it’s something we do, and have done, for a long time. True, for
many people, eating animals is a
tradition. But not all traditions are good or right: the important question is
always whether an aspect of a tradition can be supported by good moral reasons
or not. Also, for many people, eating animals is not a tradition: for thousands of years there have been people who
extend their compassion to animals, and many other people who were raised eating
animals start new traditions when they see that consistency and moral reasoning
demands change.
Second,
some people say that it’s “natural” to raise and kill animals to eat them, so
it’s right. But the meaning of “natural” is extremely obscure: people can mean
very different things when they use the term. Whatever meaning one uses,
however, it’s very hard to see how modern, industrial methods of factory
farming, transport and slaughter are at all “natural.” It’s not even clear how
an individual’s raising and killing, say, a pig or a chicken in her backyard
would be “natural” either.
But the
relationship between what’s “natural,” in any
sense of the term, and what’s morally right does not help this argument.
Selfishness and cruelty are often quite “natural,” but they are not right or
good. Walking on one’s hands is a quite “unnatural” way to transport oneself,
but it’s usually not wrong to do so. Some “natural” behaviors are right, but many are deeply wrong,
and advocates of this argument forget that simple point. Whether
something is “natural” or not is irrelevant to its morality.
Third, some
people insist that it’s nutritionally
necessary to eat meat, milk and eggs and, therefore, it’s right that
animals are raised and killed to be eaten. But this argument ignores common
sense and disrespects medical science. If it were true that we have to eat meat and other animal
products, then there would be no people who abstain from doing do so because
they would all be dead. But there are such people, alive and well, and medical
science supplements common observations with evidence to show that they are
often healthier than omnivores.2 Consider the position statement of
the leading authority on nutrition in North America based on their
seventeen-page review of the recent nutrition research:
It is the position of the American
Dietetic Association and Dietitians of Canada that appropriately planned
vegetarian diets are healthful, nutritionally adequate, and provide health
benefits in the prevention and treatment of certain diseases. . . Well-planned vegan and other
types of vegetarian diets are appropriate for all stages of the life cycle,
including during pregnancy, lactation, infancy, childhood, and adolescence. . .
A vegetarian, including vegan, diet can meet current recommendations for all of
these nutrients. . . Vegetarian diets offer a number of nutritional benefits,
including lower levels of saturated fat, cholesterol, and animal protein as
well as higher levels of carbohydrates, fiber, magnesium, potassium, folate,
and antioxidants such as vitamins C and E and phytochemicals. Vegetarians have
been reported to have lower body mass indices than nonvegetarians, as well as
lower rates of death from ischemic heart disease; vegetarians also show lower
blood cholesterol levels; lower blood pressure; and lower rates of
hypertension, type 2 diabetes, and prostate and colon cancer.3
So this
defense of eating animals is either ignorant of, or disrespectful towards, the
huge (and growing) body of research that shows the health benefits from eating
a diet based on vegetables, legumes, fruits and whole grains, and ignores the
growing literature detailing the variety of harms for humans that can result
from the production and consumption of animal products.4 This
argument thus has a false empirical premise: it is not supported by science and
medical research.
A pattern
is emerging, and we can use it to make a point about how to critically respond
to reasoning given in ethics. There are two useful critical ways to respond to
moral arguments: an “Oh yeah?” response, and a “So what?” response. The former
“Oh yeah?” response denies the truth of the premise and the latter “So what?”
response denies the truth of the (often unstated) assumption needed to validly
reach the conclusion. We can see these helpful responses in action by
considering more arguments in favor of harming animals.
A fourth
argument is based in the claim that “meat tastes good” or that it is
pleasurable to eat it. But so what?
Just because something causes pleasure doesn’t make it right. We do not think
that pleasures automatically justify
harming humans: if things are
different in the animal case, we need reasons to see why this would be so. And,
besides, there are many other pleasure-producing cuisines (often they are
ethnic) to choose from that aren’t based on animal products anyway.
A fifth
argument is based on someone’s claiming that he or she “just couldn’t give up
meat or dairy products or eggs.” Oh yeah?
Since so many other people have given these up, or never ate them in the first
place, this claim is likely disingenuous. And since this person probably hasn’t
even tried changing his or her diet for moral reasons, he or she likely lacks
the evidence needed to confidently make that judgment.
Sixth,
people claim that animals eat other animals, so it’s right for us to do. Oh yeah? Only some animals eat other animals, and these are not chickens, pigs or
cows. And so what? Many animals do
lots of things that we wouldn’t want to do, and should not do (e.g., eat their
own excrement and, sometimes, their young), so why should we imitate animals in
only some ways, but not others? A principled
response is needed for this argument to have any force.
Sometimes
people say that we are animals,
thinking that this justifies our killing and eating animals. But it does not:
just because we are animals does not
mean that it’s morally right for us to do all
the other things that other animals do; above we saw many things that (some)
animals do that would be wrong for us to do. And if we are animals, we are
unique animals with the ability to reason about the morality of our actions, in
light of their consequences for others. Should not we use this reason to do
what reduces harms to animals and ourselves?
Seventh,
people say eating meat is “convenient.” Oh
yeah? Many meat-based dishes are inconvenient
to prepare, and plant-based dishes are usually as convenient as eating meat anyway. It’s just a matter of choosing
something else from the same menu or same grocery store. But since doing the
right thing sometimes requires our
being inconvenienced in minor (and sometimes major) ways, so what?
Eighth, it
is sometimes said that we have a right
to treat animals these ways, and that animals have no rights to not be treated these ways. That might be true, but
reasonable people want reasons for
why they should think that. First, they will want to know what “right” is under
consideration. Suppose it’s the right to
not be caused to suffer and die for someone else’s pleasure. Is it because
animals don’t do math problems, write novels or make moral decisions that they
don’t have this right? If so, since babies and many other humans don’t (and,
for some, can’t) do these things, this view about moral rights denies them
rights also.
Is it
because animals are not biologically
human that they lack the right to not be harmed for others? Interestingly,
nearly all philosophers who have considered these issues reject this kind of
theory: on their views, the fact that we are biologically human has little to
do with what we are owed, morally. This hypothesis is confirmed, in part, by
each of us asking us what it is about
ourselves that, e.g., makes it such
that it would be wrong to cause us pain and kill us. For most people, the
obvious explanation is that this would hurt greatly, we would suffer enormously
and our early deaths would prevent us from experiencing all the good things we
(hopefully) would have experienced. It’s not because of some genes we have or
where we are on some chart in a biology book that explains our moral status;
rather, it is a matter of our vulnerability to physical and/or psychological
harm.
But since
many animals are also vulnerable to such harms, these animals seem to be due
the respect due to, at least, comparably-minded
humans. Since this respect requires not raising and killing these humans
for the mere pleasures of eating
them, rational consistency requires the same treatment for chickens, cows, pigs
and other animals who often have far richer mental lives than many humans.
Farming
Facts
These are
just a few of the more common arguments given in defense of raising and killing
animals for food. The fact that they are all quite weak suggests that people’s
resistance to change regarding these issues might be based on non-rational
influences, not critical thinking and unbiased inquiry. But the fact that a
strong defense of the status quo is
lacking does not give us yet enough positive reason to think that animals are
treated wrongly.
To see these reasons, we must consider in brief detail how are animals
are harmed so that they might be served on our plates.
The
treatment of animals in farms and slaughterhouses has been well documented by all major print and television media.[2]
On both “factory” and the few remaining “family” farms,
baby animals are castrated, branded, ear and tail docked, and teeth are pulled,
all without (costly) anesthesia. “Veal” calves, the male by-products of the
dairy industry, spend their entire life individually chain at the neck and
confined to narrow stalls too narrow for them to turn around in. “Broiler”
chickens, due to selective breeding and growth promoting drugs, are killed at forty-five
days. Such fast growth causes chickens to suffer from a number of chronic
health problems, including leg disorders and heart disease. “Layer” hens live a
year or more in cages the size of a filing drawer, seven or more per cage,
after which they routinely are starved for two weeks (“force molted”) to
encourage another laying cycle. Female hogs are housed for four or five years
in individual barred enclosures ("gestation stalls") barely wider
than their bodies, where they are forced to birth litter after litter. Until
the recent “Mad Cow” scare, beef and dairy cattle too weak to stand (“downers”)
were dragged or pushed to their slaughter.[3]
Many people would describe the treatment of animals in
slaughterhouses as simply brutal: the title of a 2001 Washington Post entitled “The Die Piece by Piece: In Overtaxed Plants, Humane Treatment of Cattle
is Often a Battle Lost,” is suggestive of standard operating procedures in
American slaughterhouses; more recent stories reveal similar inhumane
conditions. A 2004 New York Times story
documented workers at a chicken slaughterhouse stomping on chickens, kicking
them, and violently slamming them against floors and walls. Those attentive to
the news media see stories like this all too often.
One hopes
that this treatment is not routine, but there are is good reason to be
skeptical of claims that it is not. After all, there are no laws protecting
farmed animals, since they are explicitly excluded from the Animal Welfare Act.
The Act says that, “the term ‘animal’ ... excludes horses not used for research
purposes and other farm animals, such as, but not limited to, livestock or
poultry, used or intended for food.”
Reasonable
Ethics
So should
we think that the harmful treatment of animals in farms and slaughterhouses is
wrong and should not be supported? This conclusion follows only when moral principles are conjoined with
facts about animal agribusiness and, perhaps, the fact that we do not need to
eat animal products to survive and thrive.
Fortunately,
complex moral thinking is not needed to find plausible principles to apply to
this case. The simple, but powerful, “common sense” principle that we should avoid inflicting and supporting
needless harm is all that is needed, and is supported by a wide range of
theoretical perspectives – secular and religious – in ethics (in fact, nearly
all of them). These theories urge that we should promote goodness and lessen
badness or evil, respect all beings
who are conscious and sentient (not just those who are “rational”), treat
others as we would like to be treated, and otherwise promoting caring,
compassionate, sympathetic, sensitive and fair attitudes and behavior. All of
these theories condemn the practices of contemporary animal agribusiness.
This is
true of both secular and religious moral points of view. About Christianity, It
is very doubtful that Jesus – who advocated compassion, love and mercy – would support
the needless killing of animals for pleasure. Christian theologians and
philosophers have carefully engaged these issues and have argued that theology,
the Bible and critical thinking about God’s will likely supports such
compassion.[4]
For those who insist that God supports killing animals for the pleasure of
eating them, we need to ask them, first, how they might know that and, second,
what reasons God would have for
advocating eating animals, especially since it is often nutritional harmful for
humans.
Perspectives
that deny that we should avoid inflicting needless harm typically degenerate
into infantile “might-make sright” moral theories or they falsely imply that
it’s only because “rational agents”
care about non-rational beings (humans and animals) that it’s be wrong to harm
these beings. This latter thought is mistaken because it’s wrong to harm these
beings because they can be harmed,
not because harming them would upset us.
Thus, it
seems that reasonable humans (all of whom have to eat and can easily choose animal-free foods; they cannot claim they are
“too busy” to refrain from eating animals or that there are “more important
things” to do, so they therefore must
eat animals) should broaden their serious
moral concern to include conscious, sentient beings who are not human:
reasonable people should not eat animals, since this is what the best moral
reasons support.
One final
response to arguments for vegetarianism is a response common to many arguments
about issues that challenge how we live our lives: “People are going to believe whatever they want to believe,
and people are going to do whatever
they want to do.” It’s important to realize that this response is lamentable:
it’s an evasion of the issues, since it does not engage the arguments. For this
issue, it’s an attempt to avoid rational engagement with uncomfortable
questions about the lives and deaths of, each years, tens of billions of
conscious, feeling beings.
Those who
are committed to the value of reason in guiding our beliefs, attitudes, and
even our feelings should discourage this response, and promote reasonableness
in all things, not just a select few,
personally-convenient, topics. They should do this also because this response
is false: people sometimes do change
their beliefs and behaviors, and on the basis of good reasons. This is true
about many issues, and confronting ethical issues about animals can often help
us better see this for, and in, ourselves.
The ultimate measure of
a man is not where he stands in moments of comfort and convenience, but where
he stands at times of challenge and controversy.
- Martin
Luther King Jr.
[1] Peter Singer, Animal Liberation, 3 Ed. (New York: HarperCollins
Publishers, 2002), p. 95.
[2] For reviews of this media
coverage, see, among many other sources,
Dawn Animal World News Watch (www.DawnWatch.com) and
Vegan
Outreach’s E-newsletter (www.veganoutreach.org/enewsletter).
[3] For documentation and
further information, see the literature produced by Vegan Outreach (www.VeganOutreach.org)
and Compassion Over Killing (www.COK.net and www.TryVeg.com).
[4] See The Christian Vegetarian Association at www.ChristianVeg.com for an overview of this discussion and
literature.
No comments:
Post a Comment