George's views about embryo research (and abortion) appeal to the same kind of "kind" argument: embryos are the "kind" of being that has a "rational nature." Yet embryo's are not rational, or not yet rational, and so this view seems problematic also. Years ago I wrote this paper discussing George's arguments. I re-post it here in case reading it would improve discussion of each "kind" argument, about embryo research and marriage:
Critical Study of Robert P. George and Christopher Tollefsen, Embryo: A Defense of Human Life
Abstract: In Embryo: A Defense of Human Life (Doubleday, 2008), Robert P. George and Christopher Tollefsen argue that human embryo-destructive experimentation is morally wrong and should not be supported with state funds. I argue that their arguments are unsuccessful.
I never really tried to publish this paper because I found this book a few years after it was published and so by that point I thought there wouldn't be much interest in a longer critical review anywhere.
For discussion of similar arguments, see my "Abortion, Metaphysics and Morality: A Review of Francis Beckwith’s Defending Life: A Moral and Legal Case Against Abortion Choice."
Full paper below:
Human
Embryos, Personhood and Death:
A Critical
Study of Robert P. George and Christopher Tollefsen, Embryo: A Defense of Human Life
Nathan Nobis
1.
INTRODUCTION
In Embryo: A Defense of Human Life (Doubleday, 2008), Robert P. George
and Christopher Tollefsen (hereafter ‘G & T’) argue that human
embryo-destructive experimentation is morally wrong and should not be supported
with state funds.
Although both authors are
Catholic, and the New York Times
describes George as the “most influential conservative Christian thinker”1
in the United States, their arguments are entirely secular: they do not appeal
to any theological, scriptural, ecclesiastical, or otherwise
religiously-oriented concerns in making their case.2 Their
arguments, however, are ones that many people, especially people of with
“conservative” religious commitments, find appealing; furthermore, their case
might influence social policy; indeed, perhaps it does.3 For these
reasons, in addition to purely philosophy
and moral interest, their arguments are worthy of careful examination.
Embryo experimentation is often
defended by appealing to the medical benefits for children and adults that
might come from it. G & T argue, however, that such benefits would not
justify embryo experimentation: appeals to “the greater good” would not justify
terminal experimentation on mentally retarded infants, and appeals to benefits
do not justify embryo experimentation either (pp. 5-6).
Thus, they argue that embryos
ought not to be used, to invoke Kantian terminology, as “mere means” towards
others’ ends: they have a moral right
to life that trumps potential benefits for others. To state their position
simply, they argue that embryos have this moral status because they are human beings,
because they are this “kind” of
being.
Here I summarize their case
(which implies that abortion is immoral as well). While G & T admirably
explain why many arguments in favor of embryo experimentation fail,4
I argue that their arguments against embryo experimentation are unsuccessful.
Thus, they do not give good reasons to believe that embryo experimentation is
wrong and should be legally prohibited.
2.
BIOLOGY & METAPHYSICS
Much of G & T’s discussion
defends two non-moral claims. First, that we – people like you and I – were embryos, that each of us is
numerically identical to the embryo that was us at an earlier stage of our
development. Second, that human embryos
are “human beings.”
This second claim strikes me as
obviously true, given even a relatively unsophisticated biological
understanding of embryos and their development.5 On any plausible
suggestions or analyses of what it is to be
a “being,” embryos seem to be beings: what else would they be? And human embryos obviously are biologically human: they are not feline
or bovine. So human embryos are “human beings,” in one clear sense of the term.6
The first claim, that we are
numerically identical to embryos, is dubious, but innocuous, I will argue.
The book opens with a story of
“Noah,” a boy who developed from an embryo “rescued” from Hurricane Katrina
(pp. 1-3). It is said that his life, he, was saved from the Hurricane and so
he is numerical identical to that
embryo.
Of course, each of us, given
actual biological reality, is related
to an embryo, in that had that it been
destroyed or never come into being in the first place we would not exist.7
But that needn’t mean that any of us are numerically identical to past fetuses,
despite our bodies being spatiotemporally
continuous with them. About Noah, we could say that some of the physical
materials that were necessary for his existence were saved from the Hurricane,
but that he emerged later, perhaps
when consciousness emerged, so he is
not numerically identical to that embryo. Similar claims can be made about any
normal child or adult: we came to exist after our biological organisms came to
exist.
Indeed, such an account is
preferable. One reason (beyond the simpler Lockean “Prince and the Pauper” case
or Disney’s “Freaky Friday” case) comes from Noah’s stepping into a
Parfit-inspired malfunctioning “Teletransporter” and two (or more!) individuals
emerging on the Moon and Mars who, until that point, shared a psychology. To
many people, it seems that these individuals would be related to Noah in all
morally and prudentially relevant ways, yet not identical to him (since if they
were, then they’d be identical to each other, which is impossible given their
different locations). These theories hypothesize that psychological continuity,
not bodily continuity, is what makes for what’s
ordinarily called “personal identity” (or another close relation). These
theories imply that we – essentially psychological beings – are not numerically
identical to embryos, given their lack of psychologies: we were never
pre-conscious embryos.
I believe psychology-based
theories of identity, which can be supported with additional arguments,8
are the more plausible views and so that G & T are mistaken on the
metaphysics of what “we” are: we are not functioning biologically human organisms
essentially.
But this is metaphysics and
thereby deeply controversial. However, nothing is immediately lost or gained by
the foe or friend of embryo experimentation by granting this metaphysics or denying it: it is morally inert.9
To see why, suppose it is true. One might think that, since we are persons
now with various moral rights, if we are identical to embryos, then they also were persons (and current embryos are persons) with such rights as well.
But this does not immediately follow since it is not true that all properties, or all moral properties, possessed by adults are also had by children,
or by embryos.10 Thus, even if embryos and children and adults are
numerically identical, this does not, in itself, show that embryos have the
moral status G & T claim they do.
Suppose, however, that we are not identical to embryos, as I argued.
Some might see this as a theoretical loss for the critic of embryo
experimentation, but it needn’t be. Non-identity does not preclude embryos from
perhaps having some other property(s) that makes them seriously wrong to
destroy, e.g., as having valuable futures, as being potential persons, as
material to bring about future possible persons, and other possibilities. So
denying identity doesn’t make profound criticism of embryo experimentation
impossible.11
3.
“MORAL DUALISM” VERSUS MORAL MONISM
Nevertheless, I propose that we
accept, at least for the sake of argument, that we are identical to embryos,
that we once were embryos, since, at least, G & T think (erroneously, in my
view) that this is important. But why then is embryo experimentation wrong?
G & T’s main claims,
repeated throughout the book, is that this is because embryos are biologically human organisms, human beings, with
“basic natural capacities for characteristically human functions,” “radical”
capacities for such “mental acts,” that, if all goes well, develop by their
“nature” through a “self directed
process” until these capacities become “immediately accessible” (pp. 79-80).
Embryos are wrong to destroy because they are this “kind” of being, members of
the “natural kind” the human species, which has these characteristics,
including a “rational nature” (p. 112). Because of all this they claim there is “little mystery” that embryos are persons
(p. 80) and worthy of “full moral respect” (p. 82).
There is mystery here. Someone can
recognize that embryos have all the non-moral, biological properties that G
& T observe that they have, including that they are beings that are human
or human beings, but reasonably deny their view about what might be called
embryos’ “moral status,” including whether they are persons.
G & T repeatedly emphasize
what embryos are, what kind of beings they are, and claim that
the relevant description is like what’s given above. But embryos are of many other
kinds also, e.g., the kind “pre-conscious and never-been-conscious being.” One
can argue that since this is (among other true descriptions) what embryos are, what kind they are, that they are not
persons, not valuable in a way that
contributes to their being wrong to kill and so not prima facie impermissible to destroy.
G & T label views that
offer this kind of response “Moral Dualisms.” I prefer to call them versions of
“Mentalism” because they hold that what makes a life valuable is its mental qualities, e.g., consciousness,
sentience, an inner life, subjective states of well-being, and so forth. On
such a view, beings prior and post mental lives lack properties that make them
prima facie wrong to destroy since,
in part, such beings cannot be harmed yet or any more, i.e., be made worse off
than they are: regarding embryos, they lack a baseline consciousness to be made
worse off from and so destroying them does not harm them.
G & T presumably call such
views “Dualisms” because they distinguish the biologically human organism, the
properties that can make such organisms morally valuable, persons, and/or due
obligations and recognize the possibility and common actuality of the former
physical states without the latter moral states (pp. 112-116). Although they do
not call their own view a “Moral Monism,” their main, but not sole, support for
it seems to come from arguments against Dualisms. I will argue that their main
arguments against Moral Dualism are weak: at least some Dualists, Mentalists,
have plausible replies.
Arguments from End of Life – Beginning of Life Asymmetry
A
first argument from G & T against Mentalism is that arguments that
might be developed from its judgments about end
of life cases have false implications for beginning
of life cases.
To understand, suppose that you
were smashed by a bus, your higher brain irreparably destroyed (and so rendered
“brain dead” in any relevant sense of the term), but that your body remains
alive with a heart-beat, breathing and whatnot. Would it be permissible
to eventually “let your body die” once, say, it is certain enough that there is
no hope of recovery, your friends and relatives have visited and so on? Many
people would say, “Yes.” Could it be permissible to “actively” kill your body?
Many, although perhaps fewer, people would also say, “Yes.” Many
people would support these judgments by claiming that there no longer is a person here: the person is permanently
gone, which is why others are (hopefully) sad about our death. There is only a
“vegetable,” an irreversibly unconscious
being now and, while there can be obligations concerning vegetables, there are none towards them.
According
to G & T, this lack of personhood-based explanation would be mistaken.12
They suggest that it is permissible to end bodies’ lives like these not because they’re not persons, but because such damage has “destroy[ed] the capacity
for self-directed integral organic functioning of human beings who have matured
to the stage at which the brain performs the key role in integrating [and
unifying] the organism” (p. 133).
Which explanation, if any, is
correct? It seems to me that G & T’s complex explanation supports thinking
that there is no person, but although they might deny this: they neither assert
nor deny that such a being is a person. But they report that someone who judges
that there is no person here might reason this way: “if a human being is no
longer a person with rights once the brain has irreversibly ceased functioning,
then surely a human being in not a person
prior to the development of the brain” (p. 133). A Mentalist who thinks human
lives are morally valuable because of their mental states would think something
like this and so conclude that embryos are not persons.
G & T think that Mentalisms’s implications here are mistaken and
so Mentalism is false. But their reasoning is not very forceful because they do
not offer convincing reasons that embryos are
persons: they point out that there are differences between end of life and
beginning of life cases: e.g., embryos have various potentials, capacities, are
biologically alive, are not physically damaged and so forth, whereas beings
with destroyed brains and corpses do not have these characteristics. While this
is all true, it is not clear how this supports thinking that embryos are
persons, since, in general, potential X’s are not actual X’s, things with the
capacity to Y needn’t actually Y, living things needn’t be persons and so
forth. So their discussion here does not help refute Dualism or Mentalism.
Arguments from Sleeping and Comatose Individuals
A
second argument against Mentalism is based on G & T’s observation
that everyone must be able to explain why killing sleeping and reversibly
comatose individuals is wrong (p. 177).
They claim that such beings are persons13 and are wrong to kill
because of their “capacities” or “potentials” for mental functions (p. 118).
They argue that if potentials make these beings persons, then potentials make
embryos persons as well: Mentalisms deny
this, so Mentalisms are false.
G & T categorize sleeping
individuals as having an “immediate” or “proximate” capacity for consciousness,
comatose individuals’ capacities less immediate, and embryos’ capacities as
“radical,” but as “basic,” “natural” capacities nevertheless (p. 118). For
Mentalists, these unavoidably vague classifications of capacities might suggest
these principles:
If a being has been conscious and has some “immediate”-enough capacity for
consciousness, then that being is prima facie wrong to kill.
If a being has not been conscious, then that being is not prima facie wrong to
kill.
These principles undercut some
opposition to embryo experimentation: the second implies that “radical” and
“basic” capacities, even if “natural,” are morally irrelevant if they have never been exercised. This
is true of embryos, and so the principle implies that embryos are prima facie
permissible to destroy.
G & T object to the
proposal that “immediate” capacities (of previously conscious but currently not
conscious beings, such as the sleeping and temporarily comatose) are morally
relevant whereas non-immediate capacities (of never been but potentially
conscious beings, such as embryos) are not. Their objections are weak.
First, they claim that
Mentalists require sophisticated
mental capacities to serve as the morally relevant “immediate” capacities (p.
119). They argue that since infants and children don’t have these capacities,
such theories cannot protect infants and children, so they are false. But Mentalisms that emphasize more basic
capacities, e.g., consciousness and sentience, have no such implications. So
this objection is weak since it hits implausible versions of Mentalism.
The second objection (pp.
119-121) is more complex and, to my mind, cryptic. First, G & T claim that
capacities and potentials are on a “continuum.” This seems plausible, insofar
as there is actually having some
property and potentially having it in
more and less immediate ways, e.g., for most of us, our potential for hopping
on one foot is more immediate and easily actualizable
than our potential for visiting Antarctica or, more so, the moon. So perhaps this can be seen as a continuum ranging from actually having a
property to having it only in potentiality, in stronger and (unlimitedly?)
weaker potential.
Second, there is the claim that
are only differences in “degree” (and not “kind”) between beings that have only
“radical” capacities compared to beings with “immediate” capacities.
It is not clear what to make of
this claim about kinds: while a human
being that could or would become conscious in nine months is the same kind of being as a human being who
will become conscious in nine minutes, it is a different kind of being also. So while embryos and adults are the
same kind of beings, they are different
kinds too: this is true of just about everything insofar as each thing is
similar and different to anything else. Since embryos and conscious human
beings are of a same kind – the kind
“human being” – their remarks here are presumably most relevant (p. 120):
“[T]he difference between a being that
deserves full moral respect and a being that does not (and can therefore
legitimately be disposed of . .) cannot consist only in the fact that, while
both have some feature [e.g., ‘the development of a basic natural capacity’],
one has more of it than another.”
“A mere quantitative difference (having
more or less of the same feature, such as the development of a basic natural
capacity) cannot by itself be a justificatory basis for treating different
entities in radically different ways.”
“[B]etween the embryonic human being and
the same human being at any later stage of its maturation, there is only a
difference of degree [of ‘the development of a basic natural capacity’]” that
is morally irrelevant.
Mentalists mistakenly focus on “a mere
quantitative difference,” an accidental characteristic between conscious humans
and embryos.
It is not clear why we should
think any of the claims above are true: applied to the context of this debate,
the first claims appear to assert an assumption
that potentials are morally relevant, but that is what is at issue: since, in
general, potential X’s do not have the (moral or legal) rights of actual X’s
and we are not obligated to treat potential X’s as actual X’s (e.g.,
presidents, graduates, criminals, parents, etc.), it seems that potentials are
not morally relevant.14 G & T do not explain why (and when) they
are morally relevant.
G & T seem to argue that if
principles like these above were true, then racism would be justified: racists
argue that “differences of degree” in skin color (assuming this makes sense)
are morally relevant, but since racism is wrong, differences “of degree” are –
G & T seem to argue – generally
morally irrelevant. But this does not follow: just because some kind of
properties are sometimes irrelevant
doesn’t mean they always are or must be. But since actually possessed skin
colors are very different from properties related to potentials and capacities
for consciousness, any analogies here are quite uncertain.
Thus, it is hard to find clear reasons in G & T’s discussion
here to reject Mentalism: at least, more explanation and defense is needed. But
if they think that anyone who thinks it’s wrong to kill sleeping and comatose
individuals must think that it’s
wrong to kill embryos as well – there are no plausibly relevant difference to
appeal to, such as previously possessed
consciousness and personhood – they appear to be mistaken.
Arguments from Exploitation and Inequality
A final argument against
Dualism or Mentalism from G & T is this: they claim that if moral status is
determined by properties that come in “degrees,” e.g., consciousness or
sentience (if these properties come
in degrees), then “no account could
be given of why basic rights are not possessed by human beings in varying
degrees” (p. 121, emphasis mine), and so claims to human equality are “lies”
and so mental sophisticates would be entitled to exploit mental
simpletons.
This is mistaken. Accounts can
easily be given, and have been given, that explain
the wrongness of such exploitation: e.g., one is if an individual has the
morally relevant property (or properties) at
all, e.g., is conscious, is sentient, then that individual has an equal right
to respectful treatment, a right to not be used as a mere means for others’ ends. Such egalitarian views are
well-developed and defended in, at least, the Ethics and Animals literature,
which G & T do not discuss.15
And these views can accept the
language that they are fond of: that beings have their moral status “by virtue
of the kind of being they are” (p. 121) “what
they are” (p. 122), and the like: they just disagree about the relevant kinds,
properties and descriptions for the individuals in question. G & T claim
that “the nature of a being entity – the kind of thing it is – is established
by its characteristic actions and reactions and regular properties” (p. 183).
Mentalists needn’t disagree.
4.
CONCLUSION
In conclusion, I have reviewed
what seem to be G & T’s main claims for what it is about human embryos that would make them wrong to destroy. I have
argued that their arguments don’t succeed: they seem to describe the biology of
embryos and then assert that they are persons with a right to life and so forth
because of their potentials. They seem to suggest that denying this, by
accepting a version of Dualism or Mentalism, must lead to repugnant conclusions
for less controversial ethical issues, but this is not the case.
Their
main positive argument in favor of their Monism might be an argument from the
best moral explanation: that that property of “being a human being” is a part
of the best moral explanation why various actions are wrong. They argue that
racism, sexism and other clear cases of human exploitation are wrong because of the victim’s “humanity”: they
write, “What matters is the fact of humanity and not any other property” (p.
114). This seems false, and would seem
more obviously false if we encountered friendly, intelligent, harm-able space
aliens: they would not be human beings, but exploiting them would be wrong. The
same is true of many non-human animals. In these cases, “humanity” is
irrelevant since absent and other species- and biologically neutral properties
relevant are, e.g., mental properties relevant to harm and benefit, as Mentalisms hold.
If this is all so, then G &
T lack adequate support when they claim that the right to life “belongs to a
human being at all times that he or she exists, not just during certain stages
of his or her existence . . by virtue of
additional, accidental properties” (p. 117).16 They do not give
convincing reasons to deny, as Mentalists argue, that organisms, including
human beings, are valuable when and because they have such accidental properties
and not valuable when they have not had them. Thus, their arguments
against embryo experimentation are unsuccessful.17
Notes
1. David D. Kirkpatrick, “The
Conservative-Christian Big Thinker,” NY Times, December 16, 2009, p. MM24. Available at http://www.nytimes.com/2009/12/20/magazine/20george-t.html
2. Ever since Euthyphro this
strategy has been wise since any moral judgments said to be justified by
theological, scriptural, ecclesiastical, etc. authorities will be either
ultimately supported by good reasons or not: if not, then the judgment is
groundless, but if there are such good reasons, then these reasons are what
justifies the appeal, not the authority. For criticisms of this reasoning and a
defense of theistic ethics, however, see Matthew Carey Jordan’s “Theistic
Ethics,” Philo, 2009, Volume 12, Number 1.
3. Francis Beckwith’s arguments
in his Defending Life: A Moral and Legal
Case Against Abortion (Cambridge University Press, 2007) are similar to
George and Tollefsen’s. For a critical review of these arguments, see my “Abortion, Metaphysics and Morality: A
Review of Francis Beckwith’s Defending Life: A Moral and Legal Case Against
Abortion Choice.” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 36.3
(2011): 261-273. Beckwith is well
known as a Catholic philosopher: see his Return
to Rome: Confessions of an Evangelical Catholic (Brazos, 2008) and Politics for Christians: Statecraft as
Soulcraft (Intervarsity Press, 2010). I emphasize that my point here is not
an “ad hominem” attack on Catholics, “conservative” Christians or anybody else;
it is simply that, for whatever reasons, members of these groups tend to find
certain moral positions and arguments attractive, seemingly more so than people
who are not members of these religious groups, and so their arguments are
worthy of consideration, especially insofar as they might influence social
policy.
4. For examples, G & T
refute what they call the “Attribution View,” that what makes someone is a person is the “decision” of others (pp.
124-132). While they don’t argue in this way, any such decision will be made on
the basis of reasons or not: if there are no reasons, then anything could be a person, which is false; if a decision is made
for reasons, then those reasons, i.e., the properties of the being in question,
determine whether something is a person, not anyone’s decisions, and so the
Attribution View is false. G & T also show that none of these
considerations show that embryos are permissible to kill:
·
that few people grieve over the loss of embryos
(pp. 135-136) since few people grieve the deaths of people in absolute poverty
(or, we should add, animals brutally killed for pleasure) but they are wrong to
kill;
·
that embryos are often “naturally” lost (pp.
136-138) since what happens “naturally” is often impermissible for us to
intentionally bring about;
·
that many would save born persons from death
instead of embryos in a forced choice scenario, e.g., a burning building, since analogous forced choices
between friends and strangers don’t justify killing strangers in safe contexts
(pp. 138-142).
5. G & T report that twenty
years ago few philosophers and scientists denied that embryos were human
beings, although some argued that they are not persons (p. 174). They suggest
that tendencies to deny this coincide
with interests in embryo experimentation, suggesting that, for some, a moral
agenda influences the perception of the scientific facts. The question of
whether embryos are “human beings” is non-scientific, however, to the extent
that what is and can be a “being” is a non-scientific, philosophical issue.
6. Some common attempts to deny
this (which are often made about human fetuses as well), e.g., by observing
that they aren’t able to reason, don’t communicate, don’t contribute to
society, and so forth, overlook that there can be human beings who or that do none
of these things.
7. This seems perhaps incorrect, very strictly
speaking: could I exist had a
different embryo been fertilized or fertilized by a different sperm? (Could I exist had I come to exist without an
embryo at all?) Answers here depend on what ‘I’ refers to: it could refer to that particular
embryo and sperm combination, or some
fertilized egg or other, or various other possibilities, some of which will
entail that particular embryo is essential to that organism’s identity and
others for which it is not.
8. See Ted Sider’s chapter
“Personal Identity” in his and Earl Conee’s Riddles
of Existence (Oxford, 2005).
9. For additional
support-providing discussion, see Earl Conee’s “Metaphysics and the Morality of
Abortion,” Mind, October 1999, pp.
619-646: “Conclusions about the morality of abortion have been thought to
receive some support from metaphysical doctrines about persons. The paper
studies four instances in which philosophers have sought to draw such morals
from metaphysics. It argues that in each instance the metaphysics makes no
moral difference, and the manner of failure seems indicative of a general
epistemic irrelevance of metaphysics to the moral issue.” See also David
Shoemaker’s Personal Identity and Ethics:
A Brief Introduction (Broadview, 2008).
10. This appears to be Judith Thompson’s point (quoted on p. 116), that
adults and children (and fetuses and embryos) can have different rights and sometimes
do, so even if adults and embryos are numerically identical that needn’t entail
that embryos are persons. G & T seem to misinterpret this, however, as an
assertion that fetuses and embryos do not have a moral right to life, which
does not follow from this observation.
11. G & T deny this in claiming that if
embryos are not persons or the same “kind” of being we are, then “it would be
difficult to see why they should be accorded the same moral respect that we,
authors and readers, believe we are entitled to,” because there would be no
“obvious reason” why embryos should be protected (p. 61). While such reasons
might not be obvious, there are
candidates.
12. G & T claim that
“prevailing law and medical practice” agree with their explanation (and deny
the lack-of-personhood-based explanation), but provide no evidence of this (p. 133).
I asked a number of bioethicists and physicians if they thought there was one
standard, widely accepted moral explanation for these judgments and they all
denied that there is, citing a variety of possibly morally relevant features of
severely brain damaged or brain dead individuals.
13. Perhaps this can be denied:
these bodies could be wrong to kill even if there is no current person there;
facts about related past or future persons closely related to that body could
make these non-conscious bodies wrong to kill
14. For arguments that
potentials are morally relevant, see Bertha Manninen’s “Revisiting the argument
of fetal potential,” Philosophy, Ethics,
and Humanities in Medicine Philosophy,
2.1 (2007).
15. See, e.g., Tom Regan’s The Case for Animal Rights (University
of California Press, 1983). His Ch. 7, “Justice and Equality,” critiques
“perfectionism,” an inegalitarian view similar to what G & T falsely claim
is justified by Dualism/Mentalism.
16. Similarly, they write
“Since human beings are intrinsically valuable and deserving of full moral
respect by virtue of what they are, it follows that they are intrinsically
valuable from the point at which they come into being” (p. 123).
This comment has been removed by a blog administrator.
ReplyDelete